Cognitive Penetrability of Perception in the Age of Prediction: Predictive Systems are Penetrable Systems

被引:113
作者
Lupyan G. [1 ]
机构
[1] Department of Psychology, University of Wisconsin-Madison, Madison, WI
基金
美国国家科学基金会;
关键词
Orange Juice; Perceptual System; Perceptual State; Predictive Code; Weight Perception;
D O I
10.1007/s13164-015-0253-4
中图分类号
学科分类号
摘要
The goal of perceptual systems is to allow organisms to adaptively respond to ecologically relevant stimuli. Because all perceptual inputs are ambiguous, perception needs to rely on prior knowledge accumulated over evolutionary and developmental time to turn sensory energy into information useful for guiding behavior. It remains controversial whether the guidance of perception extends to cognitive states or is locked up in a “cognitively impenetrable” part of perception. I argue that expectations, knowledge, and task demands can shape perception at multiple levels, leaving no part untouched. The position advocated here is broadly consistent with the notion that perceptual systems strive to minimize prediction error en route to globally optimal solutions (Clark Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36(3):181–204, 2013). On this view, penetrability should be expected whenever constraining lower-level processes by higher level knowledge is minimizes global prediction error. Just as Fodor feared (e.g., Fodor Philosophy of Science 51:23–43, 1984, Philosophy of Science 51:23–43, 1988) cognitive penetration of perception threatens theory-neutral observation and the distinction between observation and inference. However, because theories themselves are constrained by the task of minimizing prediction error, theory-laden observation turns out to be superior to theory-free observation in turning sensory energy into useful information. © 2015, Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.
引用
收藏
页码:547 / 569
页数:22
相关论文
共 130 条
  • [1] Abdel Rahman R., Sommer W., Seeing what we know and understand: how knowledge shapes perception, Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 15, 6, pp. 1055-1063, (2008)
  • [2] Adelson E.H., Perceptual organization and the judgment of brightness, Science, 262, 5142, pp. 2042-2044, (1993)
  • [3] Ahissar M., Hochstein S., The reverse hierarchy theory of visual perceptual learning, Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 10, pp. 457-464, (2004)
  • [4] Amazeen E.L., Turvey M.T., Weight perception and the haptic size–weight illusion are functions of the inertia tensor, Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 22, 1, pp. 213-232, (1996)
  • [5] Anderson B., There is no such thing as attention, Frontiers in Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 2, (2011)
  • [6] Anderson B.L., Winawer J., Image segmentation and lightness perception, Nature, 434, 7029, pp. 79-83, (2005)
  • [7] Ansorge U., Becker S.I., Automatic priming of attentional control by relevant colors, Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, (2011)
  • [8] Barlow H., Conditions for versatile learning, Helmholtz’s unconscious inference, and the task of perception, Vision Research, 30, 11, pp. 1561-1571, (1990)
  • [9] Beets I.A.M., 't Hart B.M., Rosler F., Henriques D.Y.P., Einhauser W., Fiehler K., Online action-to-perception transfer: only percept-dependent action affects perception, Vision Research, 50, 24, pp. 2633-2641, (2010)
  • [10] Bergson H., Matter and memory, (1911)