Investigating the Neural and Cognitive Basis of Moral Luck: It's Not What You Do but What You Know

被引:77
作者
Young L. [1 ]
Nichols S. [2 ]
Saxe R. [1 ]
机构
[1] Department of Brain and Cognitive Sciences, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA, 02139
[2] Department of Philosophy, University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ
关键词
Moral Judgment; Behavioral Experiment; Belief Justification; Moral Luck; fMRI Experiment;
D O I
10.1007/s13164-010-0027-y
中图分类号
学科分类号
摘要
Moral judgments, we expect, ought not to depend on luck. A person should be blamed only for actions and outcomes that were under the person's control. Yet often, moral judgments appear to be influenced by luck. A father who leaves his child by the bath, after telling his child to stay put and believing that he will stay put, is judged to be morally blameworthy if the child drowns (an unlucky outcome), but not if his child stays put and doesn't drown. Previous theories of moral luck suggest that this asymmetry reflects primarily the influence of unlucky outcomes on moral judgments. In the current study, we use behavioral methods and fMRI to test an alternative: these moral judgments largely reflect participants' judgments of the agent's beliefs. In "moral luck" scenarios, the unlucky agent also holds a false belief. Here, we show that moral luck depends more on false beliefs than bad outcomes. We also show that participants with false beliefs are judged as having less justified beliefs and are therefore judged as more morally blameworthy. The current study lends support to a rationalist account of moral luck: moral luck asymmetries are driven not by outcome bias primarily, but by mental state assessments we endorse as morally relevant, i. e. whether agents are justified in thinking that they won't cause harm. © 2010 The Author(s).
引用
收藏
页码:333 / 349
页数:16
相关论文
共 33 条
[1]  
Alicke M.D., Culpable control and the psychology of blame, Psychological Bulletin, 126, pp. 556-574, (2000)
[2]  
Baron J., Hershey J.C., Outcome bias in decision evaluation, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54, pp. 569-579, (1988)
[3]  
Beebe J., Buckwalter W., The epistemic side-effect effect. Mind and Language, (2010)
[4]  
Ciaramidaro A., Adenzato M., Enrici I., Erk S., Pia L., Bara B.G., Et al., The intentional network: How the brain reads varieties of intentions, Neuropsychologia, 45, 13, pp. 3105-3113, (2007)
[5]  
Cushman F., Crime and punishment: Distinguishing the roles of causal and intentional analysis in moral judgment, Cognition, 108, pp. 353-380, (2008)
[6]  
DeRose K., Contextualism and knowledge attributions, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, pp. 913-929, (1992)
[7]  
Fletcher P.C., Happe F., Frith U., Baker S.C., Dolan R.J., Frackowiak R.S.J., Frith C.D., Other minds in the brain: A functional imaging study of "theory of mind" in story comprehension, Cognition, 57, pp. 109-128, (1995)
[8]  
Gallagher H.L., Happe F., Brunswick N., Fletcher P.C., Frith U., Frith C.D., Reading the mind in cartoons and stories: An fMRI study of 'theory of mind' in verbal and nonverbal tasks, Neuropsychologia, 38, pp. 11-21, (2000)
[9]  
Gobbini M.I., Koralek A.C., Bryan R.E., Montgomery K.J., Haxby J.V., Two takes on the social brain: A comparison of theory of mind tasks, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 19, 11, pp. 1803-1814, (2007)
[10]  
Greene J.D., Sommerville R.B., Nystrom L.E., Darley J.M., Cohen J.D., An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment, Science, 293, pp. 2105-2108, (2001)